Results for 'Douglas W. Rae'

968 found
Order:
  1.  36
    Political theory and the division of labor in society: Asleep aboard the titanic and steaming into halifax.Douglas W. Rae - 1981 - Political Theory 9 (3):369-378.
  2. Rule-Consequentialism and Irrelevant Others: Douglas W. Portmore.Douglas W. Portmore - 2009 - Utilitas 21 (3):368-376.
    In this article, I argue that Brad Hooker's rule-consequentialism implausibly implies that what earthlings are morally required to sacrifice for the sake of helping their less fortunate brethren depends on whether or not other people exist on some distant planet even when these others would be too far away for earthlings to affect.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3. Perform Your Best Option.Douglas W. Portmore - 2013 - Journal of Philosophy 110 (8):436-459.
    We ought to perform our best option—that is, the option that we have most reason, all things considered, to perform. This is perhaps the most fundamental and least controversial of all normative principles concerning action. Yet, it is not, I believe, well understood. For even setting aside questions about what our options are and what our reasons are, there are prior questions concerning how best to formulate the principle. In this paper, I address these questions. One of the more interesting (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  4. Agent-Relative vs. Agent-Neutral.Douglas W. Portmore - 2021 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
    This is a general introduction to the agent-relative/agent-neutral distinction.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  5. Commonsense Consequentialism: Wherein Morality Meets Rationality.Douglas W. Portmore - 2011 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press USA.
    Commonsense Consequentialism is a book about morality, rationality, and the interconnections between the two. In it, Douglas W. Portmore defends a version of consequentialism that both comports with our commonsense moral intuitions and shares with other consequentialist theories the same compelling teleological conception of practical reasons. Broadly construed, consequentialism is the view that an act's deontic status is determined by how its outcome ranks relative to those of the available alternatives on some evaluative ranking. Portmore argues that outcomes should (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  6. Introduction.Douglas W. Portmore - 2020 - In The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. New York, USA: Oup Usa. pp. 1-21.
  7. Kantsequentialism.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    This is a draft of Chapter Three of the book I'm working on entitled: Kantsequentialism: A Morality of Ends. This chapter outlines my favored moral theory: Kantian consequentialism or Kantsequentialism, for short. This theory takes what's best from both utilitarianism and Kantianism while leaving behind the problems associated with each.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. A Comprehensive Account of Blame: Self-Blame, Non-Moral Blame, and Blame for the Non-Voluntary.Douglas W. Portmore - 2022 - In Andreas Brekke Carlsson (ed.), Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Blame is multifarious. It can be passionate or dispassionate. It can be expressed or kept private. We blame both the living and the dead. And we blame ourselves as well as others. What’s more, we blame ourselves, not only for our moral failings, but also for our non-moral failings: for our aesthetic bad taste, gustatory self-indulgence, or poor athletic performance. And we blame ourselves both for things over which we exerted agential control (e.g., our voluntary acts) and for things over (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  9. Desire fulfillment and posthumous harm.Douglas W. Portmore - 2007 - American Philosophical Quarterly 44 (1):27 - 38.
    This paper argues that the standard account of posthumous harm is untenable. The standard account presupposes the desire-fulfillment theory of welfare, but I argue that no plausible version of this theory can allow for the possibility of posthumous harm. I argue that there are, at least, two problems with the standard account from the perspective of a desire-fulfillment theorist. First, as most desire-fulfillment theorists acknowledge, the theory must be restricted in such a way that only those desires that pertain to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  10. Consequentializing moral theories.Douglas W. Portmore - 2007 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (1):39–73.
    To consequentialize a non-consequentialist theory, take whatever considerations that the non-consequentialist theory holds to be relevant to determining the deontic statuses of actions and insist that those considerations are relevant to determining the proper ranking of outcomes. In this way, the consequentialist can produce an ordering of outcomes that when combined with her criterion of rightness yields the same set of deontic verdicts that the non-consequentialist theory yields. In this paper, I argue that any plausible non-consequentialist theory can be consequentialized. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  11. (1 other version)Latitude, Supererogation, and Imperfect Duties.Douglas W. Portmore - 2023 - In David Heyd (ed.), Springer Handbook of Supererogation. Springer.
  12.  31
    The Dimensions of Consequentialism: Ethics, Equality and Risk, written by M. Peterson.Douglas W. Portmore - 2016 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 13 (6):747-750.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Welfare, Achievement, and Self-Sacrifice.Douglas W. Portmore - 2008 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 2 (2):1-29.
    Many philosophers hold that the achievement of one's goals can contribute to one's welfare apart from whatever independent contributions that the objects of those goals or the processes by which they are achieved make. Call this the Achievement View, and call those who accept it achievementists. In this paper, I argue that achievementists should accept both that one factor that affects how much the achievement of a goal contributes to one’s welfare is the amount that one has invested in that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  14.  74
    Going to School with Friedrich Nietzsche: The Self in Service of Noble Culture.Douglas W. Yacek - 2013 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 33 (4):391-411.
    To understand Nietzsche’s pedagogy of self-overcoming and to determine its true import for contemporary education, it is necessary to understand Nietzsche’s view of the self that is to be overcome. Nevertheless, previous interpretations of self-overcoming in the journals of the philosophy of education have lacked serious engagement with the Nietzschean self. I devote the first part of this paper to redressing this neglect and arguing for a view of the Nietzschean self as an assemblage of ontologically basic affects which have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Opting for the Best: Oughts and Options.Douglas W. Portmore - 2019 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    The book concerns what I take to be the least controversial normative principle concerning action: you ought to perform your best option—best, that is, in terms of whatever ultimately matters. The book sets aside the question of what ultimately matters so as to focus on more basic issues, such as: What are our options? Do I have the option of typing out the cure for cancer if that’s what I would in fact do if I had the right intentions at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  16.  89
    What economics is not: An economist's response to Rosenberg.Douglas W. Hands - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (3):495-503.
    Alexander Rosenberg (1983) has argued, contrary to his previous work in the philosophy of economics, that economics is not science, and it is merely mathematics. The following paper argues that Rosenberg fails to demonstrate either of these two claims. The questions of the predictive weakness of modern economics and the cognitive standing of abstract economic theory are discussed in detail.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17. Does the total principle have any repugnant implications?Douglas W. Portmore - 1999 - Ratio 12 (1):80–98.
    On the Total Principle, the best state of affairs (ceteris paribus) is the one with the greatest net sum of welfare value. Parfit rejects this principle, because he believes that it implies the Repugnant Conclusion, the conclusion that for any large population of people, all with lives well worth living, there will be some much larger population whose existence would be better, even though its members all have lives that are only barely worth living. Recently, however, a number of philosophers (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18.  45
    Blaug's economic methodology.Douglas W. Hands - 1984 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 14 (1):115-125.
  19. Desert, Control, and Moral Responsibility.Douglas W. Portmore - 2019 - Acta Analytica 34 (4):407-426.
    In this paper, I take it for granted both that there are two types of blameworthiness—accountability blameworthiness and attributability blameworthiness—and that avoidability is necessary only for the former. My task, then, is to explain why avoidability is necessary for accountability blameworthiness but not for attributability blameworthiness. I argue that what explains this is both the fact that these two types of blameworthiness make different sorts of reactive attitudes fitting and that only one of these two types of attitudes requires having (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  20. Ben Bradley, Well-Being and Death (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2009), pp. xxi + 198.Douglas W. Portmore - 2010 - Utilitas 22 (4):500-503.
    Review of Ben Bradley's Well-Being and Death.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  84
    The Limits of Kindness, by Caspar Hare.Douglas W. Portmore - 2015 - Mind 124 (496):1285-1288.
    A review of Caspar Hare's book The Limit of Kindness.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  23
    Placement of topic changes in conversation.Douglas W. Maynard - 1980 - Semiotica 30 (3-4).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23. Commonsense morality and not being required to maximize the overall good.Douglas W. Portmore - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 100 (2):193-213.
    On commonsense morality, there are two types of situations where an agent is not required to maximize the impersonal good. First, there are those situations where the agent is prohibited from doing so--constraints. Second, there are those situations where the agent is permitted to do so but also has the option of doing something else--options. I argue that there are three possible explanations for the absence of a moral requirement to maximize the impersonal good and that the commonsense moralist must (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Combining teleological ethics with evaluator relativism: A promising result.Douglas W. Portmore - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (1):95–113.
    Consequentialism is an agent-neutral teleological theory, and deontology is an agent-relative non-teleological theory. I argue that a certain hybrid of the two—namely, non-egoistic agent-relative teleological ethics (NATE)—is quite promising. This hybrid takes what is best from both consequentialism and deontology while leaving behind the problems associated with each. Like consequentialism and unlike deontology, NATE can accommodate the compelling idea that it is always permissible to bring about the best available state of affairs. Yet unlike consequentialism and like deontology, NATE accords (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  25. Moral Worth and Our Ultimate Moral Concerns.Douglas W. Portmore - forthcoming - Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics.
    Some right acts have what philosophers call moral worth. A right act has moral worth if and only if its agent deserves credit for having acted rightly in this instance. And I argue that an agent deserves credit for having acted rightly if and only if her act issues from an appropriate set of concerns, where the appropriateness of these concerns is a function what her ultimate moral concerns should be. Two important upshots of the resulting account of moral worth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26. (1 other version)Consequentializing.Douglas W. Portmore - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    This is an encyclopedia entry on consequentializing. It explains what consequentializing is, what makes it possible, why someone might be motivated to consequentialize, and how to consequentialize a non-consequentialist theory.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  27. Karl Popper and economic methodology: a new look.Douglas W. Hands - 1985 - Economics and Philosophy 1 (1):83-.
    Discussions of Karl Popper's falsificationist philosophy of science appear regularly in the recent literature on economic methodology. In this literature, there seem to be two fundamental points of agreement about Popper. First, most economists take Popper's falsificationist method of bold conjecture and severe test to be the correct characterization of scientific conduct in the physical sciences. Second, most economists admit that economic theory fails miserably when judged by these same falsificationist standards. As Latsis states, “the development of economic analysis would (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  28.  30
    Visual prediction as indicated by perceptual adaptation to temporal delays and discrete stimulation.Douglas W. Cunningham - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (2):203-204.
    Analogous to prism adaptation, sensorimotor compensation for existing neural delays has been clearly demonstrated. This system can also adapt to new delays, both internal and external. This seems to occur at least partially in the sensor systems, and works for discrete, stationary events. This provides additional evidence for visual prediction, but not in a manner that is consistent with spatial extrapolation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Moral Theory.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    This is the first chapter of a book that I'm writing entitled Kantsequentialism: A Morality of Ends. The chapter has six sections: (1) The Distinction between a Moral Theory and a Complete Account of Morality, (2) The Best Explanation, (3) Fitting the Data as Opposed to the Facts, (4) Epistemic Justification and Phenomenal Conservatism, (5) Neither Overfitting nor Underfitting the Data, and (6) Trusting Our Moral Intuitions. Thus, the chapter begins by providing an account of what a moral theory is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Uncertainty, Indeterminacy, and Agent-Centred Constraints.Douglas W. Portmore - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):284-298.
    Common-sense morality includes various agent-centred constraints, including ones against killing unnecessarily and breaking a promise. However, it's not always clear whether, had an agent ϕ-ed, she would have violated a constraint. And sometimes the reason for this is not that we lack knowledge of the relevant facts, but that there is no fact about whether her ϕ-ing would have constituted a constraint-violation. What, then, is a constraint-accepting theory to say about whether it would have been permissible for her to have (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31.  12
    On Student Safety and Philosophical Dialogue.Douglas W. Yacek - 2021 - Philosophy of Education 77 (3):17-20.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  76
    Causation, Explanation, and Statistical Relevance.Douglas W. Shrader - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (1):136-145.
  33.  76
    Financial stability, economic growth, and the role of law.Douglas W. Arner - unknown
    Financial crises have become an all-too-common occurrence over the past twenty years, largely as a result of changes in finance brought about by increasing internationalization and integration. As domestic financial systems and economies become more interlinked, weaknesses can significantly impact not only individual economies but also markets, financial intermediaries and economies around the world. This volume addresses the twin objectives of financial development in the context of financial stability and the role of law in supporting both. Financial stability (frequently seen (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Dual-ranking act-consequentialism.Douglas W. Portmore - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 138 (3):409 - 427.
    Dual-ranking act-consequentialism (DRAC) is a rather peculiar version of act-consequentialism. Unlike more traditional forms of act-consequentialism, DRAC doesn’t take the deontic status of an action to be a function of some evaluative ranking of outcomes. Rather, it takes the deontic status of an action to be a function of some non-evaluative ranking that is in turn a function of two auxiliary rankings that are evaluative. I argue that DRAC is promising in that it can accommodate certain features of commonsense morality (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  35.  8
    Cognition on the ground.Douglas W. Maynard - 2006 - Discourse Studies 8 (1):105-115.
    Suggesting that much of social science is still wedded to the ‘dogma of the ghost in the machine,’ I discuss my ethnomethodological and conversation analytic approach to the assembly of cognitive objects. It is important to reverse the usual social psychological metalanguage of mind causing behavior, and see how practices in interaction operate to display cognitive states of participants. Two examples are given: one in regard to the assembly of gestalts, including social actions in talk, and the other concerning the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Maximalism and Moral Harmony.Douglas W. Portmore - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (2):318-341.
    Maximalism is the view that an agent is permitted to perform a certain type of action if and only if she is permitted to perform some instance of this type, where φ-ing is an instance of ψ-ing if and only if φ-ing entails ψ-ing but not vice versa. Now, the aim of this paper is not to defend maximalism, but to defend a certain account of our options that when combined with maximalism results in a theory that accommodates the idea (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  37. Morality and Practical Reasons.Douglas W. Portmore - 2021 - Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
    As Socrates famously noted, there is no more important question than how we ought to live. The answer to this question depends on how the reasons that we have for living in various different ways combine and compete. To illustrate, suppose that I've just received a substantial raise. What should I do with the extra money? I have most moral reason to donate it to effective charities but most self-interested reason to spend it on luxuries for myself. So, whether I (...)
  38.  42
    Offering and soliciting collaboration in multi-party disputes among children (and other humans).Douglas W. Maynard - 1986 - Human Studies 9 (2-3):261 - 285.
    This paper has aimed to remedy a neglect of multi-party disputes by addressing how those involved in a two-party argument may collaborate with others who are co-present. Collaboration is a complex phenomenon. In the first place, we have seen that disputes, although initially produced by two parties, do not consist simply of two sides. Rather, given one party's displayed position, stance, or claim, another party can produce opposition by simply aligning against that position or by aligning with a counterposition. This (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  47
    Nonviolence to Animals, Earth, and Self in Asian Traditions.Douglas W. Shrader & Christopher Key Chapple - 1997 - Philosophy East and West 47 (2):274.
  40.  10
    On Predicating a Diagnosis as an Attribute of a Person.Douglas W. Maynard - 2004 - Discourse Studies 6 (1):53-76.
    This article explores the relation between ‘citing the evidence’, or implicating a particular diagnosis, and ‘asserting the condition’, or overtly predicating the diagnosis as an attribute of a person. Clinicians regularly postpone or delay asserting the condition, which is interactionally more confrontational and presumptive. They regularly do the postponement by citing the evidence prior to asserting the condition, using the evidence as kind of predecessor account for predicating the diagnosis as an attribute of the person. Citing the evidence as leading (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  55
    Sweet Tension and its Phenomenological Description: Sport, Intersubjectivity and Horizon.Douglas W. McLaughlin & Cesar R. Torres - 2011 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 5 (3):270 - 284.
    In this paper, we argue that a rich phenomenological description of ?sweet tension? is an important step to understanding how and why sport is a meaningful human endeavour. We introduce the phenomenological concepts of intersubjectivity and horizon and elaborate how they inform the study and understanding of human experience. In the process, we establish that intersubjectivity is always embodied, developing and ethically committed. Likewise, we establish that our horizons are experienced from an embodied, developing and ethically committed perspective that serves (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  42.  7
    Philosophy and the Public Realm: Proceedings of the Fifth Oneonta Undergraduate Philosophy Conference.Douglas W. Shrader (ed.) - 2001 - State University of New York Press.
    Combines the work of promising college students with essays by distinguished scholars.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  15
    Pathways to Philosophy: A Multidisciplinary Approach.Douglas W. Shrader & Ashok Kumar Malhotra - 1996 - Pearson.
    Combining classical and contemporary readings with original essays, Pathways to Philosophy offers an imaginative introduction to the art of philosophical reflection and wonderment. The collection reflects the inherent multidisciplinary nature of the field - revealing and exploring the connections between philosophy, science, and literature. All material is carefully chosen, edited, and coordinated to ensure its accessibility to readers of all levels. The result is a presentation that is engaging, provocative, and fun. There are four main sections divided into twelve chapters (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  5
    Seeds of Wisdom: Proceedings of the 1996 Undergraduate Philosophy Conference.Douglas W. Shrader (ed.) - 1997 - State University of New York Press.
    Select papers from Oneonta’s Undergraduate Philosophy Conference.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  9
    Thinking Outside the Box: Proceedings of the Sixth Oneonta Undergraduate Philsophy Conference.Douglas W. Shrader (ed.) - 2002 - State University of New York Press.
    Select essays, originally presented at the Sixth Annual Undergraduate Philosophy Conference, held in 2001 at SUNY Oneonta.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Moral reasons, overridingness, and supererogation.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    In this paper, I present an argument that poses the following dilemma for moral theorists: either (a) reject at least one of three of our most firmly held moral convictions or (b) reject the view that moral reasons are morally overriding, that is, reject the view that moral reasons override non-moral reasons such that even the weakest moral reason defeats the strongest non-moral reason in determining an act’s moral status (e.g., morally permissible). I then argue that we should opt for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Deserving to Suffer.Douglas W. Portmore - 2024 - The Journal of Ethics 28 (4):795-813.
    I argue that the blameworthy deserve to suffer in that they deserve to feel guilt, which is the unpleasant experience of appreciating one’s apparent culpability for having done wrong. I argue that the blameworthy deserve to feel guilt because they owe it to those whom they’ve culpably wronged to (a) hold themselves accountable, (b) manifest the proper regard for those whom they’ve wronged, and (c) appreciate their culpability for, and the moral significance of, their wrongdoing. And I argue that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Consequentializing agent‐centered restrictions: A Kantsequentialist approach.Douglas W. Portmore - 2023 - Analytic Philosophy 64 (4):443-467.
    There is, on a given moral view, an agent-centered restriction against performing acts of a certain type if that view prohibits agents from performing an instance of that act-type even to prevent two or more others from each performing a morally comparable instance of that act-type. The fact that commonsense morality includes many such agent-centered restrictions has been seen by several philosophers as a decisive objection against consequentialism. Despite this, I argue that agent-centered restrictions are more plausibly accommodated within a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  14
    Causal And Geometric Relations.Douglas W. Shrader - unknown
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The Logic of Negation in Early Greek and Buddhist Philosophy.Douglas W. Shrader - 1992 - In James T. H. Martin (ed.), Philosophies of being and mind: ancient and medieval. Delmar, N.Y.: Caravan Books. pp. 87--102.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 968